Cheryl Misak on Frank Ramsey's Life and Thought

Cheryl Misak on Frank Ramsey's Life and Thought

Released Tuesday, 24th September 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Cheryl Misak on Frank Ramsey's Life and Thought

Cheryl Misak on Frank Ramsey's Life and Thought

Cheryl Misak on Frank Ramsey's Life and Thought

Cheryl Misak on Frank Ramsey's Life and Thought

Tuesday, 24th September 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:02

This is Philosophy Bites with

0:04

me David Edmonds and me

0:06

Nigel Warburton. Philosophy Bites is

0:09

available at www.philosophybites.com. Frank

0:11

Ramsey was a remarkable Cambridge philosopher who

0:13

died very young. He was only 26.

0:15

In his short

0:18

life he produced a slew of brilliant

0:20

ideas, many of which are still discussed.

0:23

In this interview, in the Biobites

0:25

thread of Philosophy Bites, Sheryl

0:28

Mezak, author of Ramsey's biography,

0:30

which she's subtitled A Sheer

0:32

Excess of Powers, explores

0:35

the relationship between his life and

0:37

thought. Sheryl Mezak, welcome

0:39

to Philosophy Bites. My pleasure.

0:42

We're talking today about Frank

0:44

Ramsey. You've been on Philosophy Bites

0:47

before, also talking about Frank Ramsey,

0:49

but in particular today we're going

0:51

to be talking about how his

0:53

life affected his philosophy. Let's

0:55

not by summarising who he

0:57

was, when he lived, how

0:59

important he was. Ramsey was,

1:02

as Paul Samuelson, the

1:04

economist once said, a genius by

1:06

any test of genius. So

1:08

he died at the age of 26 in 1930.

1:11

He was a Cambridge philosopher,

1:14

economist and mathematician who

1:16

really did unbelievable things in

1:19

this very short life. There's

1:22

a branch of combinatoric mathematics

1:24

named after him, Ramsey Theory.

1:27

There are two sub-branches of

1:29

economics that he really founded,

1:31

optimal taxation theory and

1:33

optimal savings theory. In

1:36

philosophy, we also have

1:38

just a ton of things named

1:40

after him, Ramsey sentences, Ramsey conditionalisation.

1:42

My favourite is Donald

1:44

Davidson's coinage of the term,

1:46

Ramsey effect. The Ramsey effect

1:49

is when you think you've

1:51

just come up with some

1:53

absolutely stunningly brilliant, cool idea.

1:55

And it turns out that

1:57

Frank Ramsey in 1927... already

2:00

had it. So a genius

2:02

by any definition, tell me a bit

2:04

about his upbringing, his parents. So

2:07

he was a Cambridge product. His

2:09

father was a job

2:11

in mathematics Don. When I say

2:14

a job in mathematics Don, I

2:16

mean he wrote textbooks, never did

2:18

anything of major significance. So Ramsey

2:20

was much better a mathematician than

2:23

his father. His mother

2:25

was one of these

2:27

firebrand, progressive,

2:30

feminist, socialist do-gooders.

2:34

So she would take her

2:36

three children on Christmas

2:38

Day to the poor house and

2:41

they would give presents to

2:43

the poor children before they had their own

2:45

Christmas. And Ramsey really grew up with this

2:49

mother with very strong values and

2:51

he imbibed them. He adopted his

2:53

mother's values. So he became

2:55

a socialist, is that right? Because one

2:57

doesn't really equate Ramsey economics

2:59

with socialism. Yes, Ramsey

3:02

is thought of as

3:04

an economist as being a sort

3:06

of paradigm case of a utilitarian

3:09

analyzer. So he was very,

3:11

very good at making utilitarian

3:13

arguments. In fact, he's considered

3:15

the founder of rational choice

3:18

theory because he was the

3:20

first person before Difenetti, before

3:22

von Neumann and Morgenstern to

3:25

figure out how to measure partial belief,

3:27

to come up with a subjective account

3:30

of probability and show that we could

3:32

be rational by keeping our

3:34

probability measures, our belief credences

3:36

in line with the probability

3:38

calculus. But Ramsey

3:40

was very clear, even

3:42

though he did this tremendously

3:44

impressive technical thing, that

3:47

no human being could

3:49

keep their probabilities in line with

3:52

the probability calculus. He

3:54

was running around Cambridge in 1927, giving

3:56

a talk called Mathematics and Economics. economics

4:00

in which he said look this

4:02

is a highly idealized kind of

4:04

rationality that no one can measure

4:06

up to and So

4:09

he would have hated the fact that he's

4:11

considered the founder of rational choice theory

4:14

Where does the socialism of his

4:16

mother and concerns for justice then

4:19

fit into his economics? so as

4:21

an undergraduate comes into Cambridge

4:23

very young because he was always clever and

4:26

always moved ahead He

4:28

comes in as a socialist and then

4:30

he meets Morris Dobb who was an

4:32

undergraduate at the time and a communist

4:34

and Dobb takes

4:36

Ramsey to Workers

4:38

meetings and Ramsey actually does a

4:41

lot of good and very kind

4:43

of administrative work for these workers

4:45

associations taking notes

4:47

making Generalizations about

4:49

what kind of worker was more

4:51

inclined to unionization than others and

4:54

he really had his socialism cemented

4:56

as an undergraduate and

4:58

when an undergraduate he wrote a paper called

5:01

socialism and inequality Where

5:04

he argued that economists should be

5:06

socialists and then later on when

5:08

he wrote his two very famous

5:10

papers in economics They look

5:12

like straight-up Utilitarian

5:15

models, but in fact

5:17

in one of them called a mathematical

5:19

theory of savings He asks

5:22

how much a society should save for

5:24

the future And

5:26

that's not just how much money a

5:28

society should save for future generations but

5:31

how much natural resources and the like

5:34

they should save and He

5:36

was very clear that you couldn't just

5:38

run a utilitarian calculus and for instance

5:41

Discount future generations because

5:43

some war disease might come and

5:45

wipe them out So you

5:47

can't count their utility. He said no, no, no that

5:50

would be unjust so

5:52

he brought justice considerations

5:55

into his utility analyses

5:58

and they were all left-wing

6:00

welfare economics analysis.

6:04

And is there a link at all

6:06

between his socialism or perhaps more widely

6:08

putting human beings at the center of

6:11

his thinking with his philosophy as what

6:13

is his economics? Yes,

6:15

Ramsey was first

6:17

and foremost in philosophy a

6:20

pragmatist. So the pragmatist says

6:23

that when we analyze our

6:26

philosophical concepts like truth, probability,

6:31

knowledge, belief, we

6:33

mustn't go all metaphysical, but

6:36

we must start with human beings and

6:38

the role these concepts play in

6:41

human inquiry and human lives. So

6:44

Ramsey's account of probability is

6:46

a subjectivist accountability. It's about

6:48

our degrees of belief and

6:50

what they ought to be.

6:53

And his account of knowledge, he

6:55

was the first reliabilist in the

6:57

theory of knowledge. He said, we

6:59

know P when P is a

7:01

reliable belief with which we meet

7:04

the future, something that works

7:06

perfectly for us. This

7:08

stands in my contrast to Wittgenstein's

7:11

philosophy and Wittgenstein was an enormous

7:13

influence on Ramsey. Yes,

7:15

although I would argue that Wittgenstein

7:18

was an enormous influence on Ramsey

7:20

and Ramsey was an enormous influence

7:22

on Wittgenstein. So as

7:25

an undergraduate, Ramsey is

7:27

asked to translate this

7:29

manuscript that has come out of war-torn

7:31

Europe. Wittgenstein is in a

7:33

prisoner of war camp in Italy and

7:36

Russell and Keynes managed to

7:39

get this manuscript out of

7:41

Europe to Cambridge. And

7:43

it's a very unusual manuscript.

7:45

It's written as a series

7:47

of propositions with sub-propositions. It's

7:49

unlike anything that has been

7:52

seen before and

7:54

it's very technical. And Moore

7:56

says it's untranslatable. And

7:58

then they figure out, well, actually,

8:00

maybe. this young mathematically inclined genius

8:03

Frank Ramsey can translate it. And

8:05

indeed, Ramsey is very keen

8:07

to do it and he understands the philosophy

8:09

completely because he's been going to Moore's

8:12

lectures and he's been going to visit

8:14

Russell in London to talk about logic.

8:17

And Ramsey takes Wittgenstein's

8:20

manuscript in German to

8:22

the university typing office and

8:25

he reads off to mis-pate the

8:28

tractatus logical philosophicus in

8:31

English. So he looks at the German

8:33

sentence and he reads it off to

8:35

mis-pate in English. She transcribes it. They

8:37

go back and forth and Wittgenstein declares

8:40

the translation to have more

8:42

authority than the original. So

8:45

Ramsey was completely taken

8:48

by Wittgenstein's tractatus,

8:51

which is, as you

8:53

say, completely unlike Ramsey's

8:55

later pragmatist philosophy. So

8:58

Wittgenstein's argument was that the

9:00

meaning and truth of a

9:02

proposition, which is somehow some

9:04

independently existing entity, very bizarre,

9:07

but the meaning of a proposition and the truth

9:09

of proposition is that you take

9:11

a complex proposition, you boil it

9:14

down to its very simple constituents

9:16

and then each of those constituent

9:19

elements shares a logical form with

9:22

reality or a state of affairs. So it's

9:25

completely non-human kind of meaning

9:27

and truth. And Ramsey

9:30

translates a tractatus and then

9:32

immediately writes a critical notice

9:34

of it, which still stands as one

9:36

of its most important commentaries. Famously

9:39

at the end of the tractatus

9:41

there's a section about ethics and

9:43

the meaning of life. How does

9:46

Ramsey's human approach differ

9:48

from Wittgenstein? Good. Wittgenstein

9:51

in the tractatus had

9:54

a big problem in that very

9:57

few propositions are going to come out.

10:00

meaningful and true on this

10:02

strict logical picture theory of

10:04

meaning and truth. Only

10:06

very simple statements like the pen is

10:08

to the left of the cup, perhaps,

10:11

are going to share a logical form with the

10:14

state of affairs. There were

10:16

a lot of propositions like

10:18

universal generalizations, causal propositions, but

10:21

also ethical propositions and propositions

10:23

about the meaning of life that literally

10:25

just don't fit into Wittgenstein's picture. And

10:28

of propositions about the

10:30

meaning of life, Wittgenstein said, we must

10:32

be silent. We can't

10:35

say anything about the meaning of

10:37

life, but somehow our thoughts

10:41

about the meaning of life are

10:43

more important than what we can

10:45

say in this primary logical language.

10:48

So in 1925, there was a very interesting series

10:52

of papers given at the

10:54

Apostles Society in Cambridge, the

10:56

secret conversation society. So

10:59

first Russell came and talked about

11:01

the meaning of life and he

11:03

talked about how puny human beings were

11:05

in the great universe

11:08

and was eloquent as he always

11:10

was about how all

11:12

of human aspiration and accomplishment

11:16

and love is bound to

11:19

just be wiped out in

11:22

the debris of a dying universe

11:25

because the universe is going to cool and die. Now

11:29

we think it's going to heat up and die, but at the

11:32

time we're sure it was going to cool and die.

11:35

And Ramsey then gave a talk about

11:37

the meaning of life and

11:39

he said unlike some of my friends, he

11:42

didn't mention them, but he meant Russell and

11:44

Wittgenstein. He took

11:47

the human perspective He

11:49

said the stars are all

11:51

as small as threepenny bits as

11:53

far as the human is concerned. What

11:56

Ramsey was interested in was human

11:59

beings. and what was

12:01

best for human beings. So

12:03

Russell focused on the vastness of

12:06

the universe and found it depressing

12:09

when it came to the meaning of life. Wittgenstein,

12:12

on the other hand, focused on this

12:14

tight, logical language and said you couldn't

12:16

say anything about the meaning of life,

12:19

but nonetheless, he also was a massive

12:21

depressive. And Ramsey said, unlike

12:23

some of my friends, I

12:25

find life quite wonderful

12:27

and enjoyable because I take the

12:30

human perspective. Well, tell

12:32

me a bit about Ramsey's character then,

12:34

because that seems to be

12:36

connected with an attitude

12:38

to other human beings, an

12:40

enjoyment in life. Wittgenstein notoriously

12:42

was terrible with other people,

12:44

lacked empathy. Russell was more

12:46

gregarious. What about Ramsey? Ramsey,

12:49

it was very easy to write

12:52

this biography in a way because

12:54

Ramsey turned out to be the

12:56

sunniest, most lovely, lovable

12:58

character, probably in the history

13:01

of philosophy. It's very

13:03

hard to find anyone who would

13:06

say a bad word about him. So

13:09

he was warm, he was gregarious, and

13:11

he was very concerned about what

13:14

other people were feeling

13:16

in any human situation. And

13:19

this did have an influence on

13:21

his both philosophy and economics, I

13:23

think. An economist, I believe

13:25

it was Paul Samuelson, identified

13:28

one move of Ramsey's in

13:30

economics as being after the

13:32

feasible first best. And this,

13:35

I think, is

13:37

Ramsey's approach to everything

13:39

in philosophy and economics. He's not

13:41

after the ideal. So Wittgenstein was

13:43

after the ideal truth that actually

13:45

no human being can have, no

13:47

human being is going to get

13:49

their propositions such that they

13:52

share a logical form with reality. He

13:55

was against idealization in economics.

13:57

No human being is going

13:59

to be... a perfect maximizer

14:01

of utility. What Ramsey

14:04

was after was what human

14:06

beings can realistically

14:09

get to. And that's a line

14:11

of his that I employ quite

14:14

heavily in my work on Ramsey.

14:16

He was after a realistic philosophy

14:19

and a realistic economics. And I

14:21

think that is because as a

14:23

human being, he was after the

14:26

best that we human beings can do. And

14:28

you describe him as a pragmatist.

14:30

Does he come up with pragmatism

14:32

himself or is he introduced to

14:35

pragmatism by somebody else? Yes, so

14:37

he is introduced by pragmatism by

14:39

someone else. When he was a

14:41

school boy, a family

14:43

friend, Charles K. Ogden,

14:45

who was kind of a man about

14:47

town in Cambridge and a very serious

14:49

publisher, published Vickenstein's Tractatus,

14:52

for instance. Ogden was

14:54

Ramsey's mentor, took him under his wing.

14:57

And Ogden was one of

14:59

the very few people in Britain who

15:02

was really interested in and attracted

15:04

to pragmatism. And he was reading

15:07

Peirce, not understanding him very well.

15:09

Ogden wasn't a great thinker himself,

15:11

he was a great publisher. And

15:14

he put in the young Ramsey's hands

15:17

a couple of papers of Peirce's. And

15:19

then when the very first volume of Peirce's

15:21

papers were published after his death, Peirce died

15:24

in 1914, 1922, the Harcourt Brace in America

15:26

published a volume of Peirce's

15:32

papers. And Ogden published them

15:34

simultaneously in the UK. Hardly

15:37

anyone has clocked that. And

15:39

Ramsey read them hot off the press

15:42

when he was an undergraduate in 1922. And that's when he

15:45

started to call himself a pragmatist.

15:49

You've written the definitive

15:51

biography, definitely, of Ramsey.

15:54

You already knew about his philosophy, but

15:56

did writing the biography give

15:59

you new insights into

16:01

how you understood his philosophy. It

16:04

did, in that I knew he was a

16:06

pragmatist because he said he was. And

16:09

I had thought that pragmatism manifested

16:11

itself with respect to his theory

16:14

of belief and how what is

16:16

important about a belief is that it meet

16:18

the future well. So we're not

16:21

interested in that kind of correspondence theory

16:23

of truth that Wittgenstein was interested in,

16:25

but we're interested in how our beliefs

16:27

serve us well in the future. But

16:30

then it turned out when I dived into

16:33

the rest of Ramsey's thought and

16:36

also into his personality that

16:38

this idea of the feasible

16:40

first best really was

16:42

the governing thought of all

16:44

of his work, except obviously

16:47

in combinatoric mathematics. It would have really

16:49

been a stretch to try to apply

16:52

that overarching thought to Ramsey theory

16:54

in mathematics. Ciao, Ami

16:56

Sakh. Thank you very much indeed. Thank

16:58

you.

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features